Bioethicist Says Allowing Infanticide Does Not Violate a Baby’s Right to Life

International   |   Michael Cook   |   Sep 11, 2018   |   6:03PM   |   Washington, DC

Arguments which pose infanticide as a moral option have put bioethicists in hot water in recent years. But they are not going to go away. In an on-line-first article in the journal Bioethics, Norwegian bioethicist Joona Räsänen counter-attacks with a defence of the moral possibility of infanticide. (Attention, people! This does not imply a campaign to implement or legalise infanticide, only its theoretical morality.)

Räsänen first engaged with this issue in a 2016 article in Bioethics, whose assertions were questioned by several pro-life scholars, notably Christopher Kaczor. It is difficult to give a tidy summary of the the complex arguments deployed by Räsänen and his opponents, but here are some of the highlights.

First of all, he points out that he is not trying to justify infanticide. He simply wants to point out that pro-life arguments are mistaken and do not succeed in eliminating it as a morally permissible option.

Pro-life scholars contend that newborns have a right to life and that infanticide must be wrong because it violates this. Not so, responds Räsänen. There exists an argument permitting infanticide which does not deny their right to life. Since this may be quite novel to readers of BioEdge, it is worthwhile quoting in full:

But there might be an argument that gives, for example, the genetic parents a right to kill (or leave to die) their newborn infant even if the infant has a right to life. For example, it might be argued that people have a right to their genetic privacy and having the newborn infant in the world that carries the genetic material of the genetic parents violates their right to genetic privacy. Put another way: the fetus does not have a right to the genetic material of her parents.

He put this argument forward in an article in Bioethics last year in the context of ectogenesis. But what about 10-year-olds? Don’t they infringe on their parents’ privacy rights? No, says Räsänen, they have been alive longer and have “a strong time‐relative interest to continue living”.

Click here to sign up for pro-life news alerts from LifeNews.com

Pro-life arguments also involve assert that even embryos have a right to life. Räsänen subjects this to a reductio ad absurdum:

If the death of an embryo is as bad for the embryo as the death of a standard human adult is for her, it seems that spontaneous abortions are one of the most serious illnesses of our time, and if we do nothing to stop them we are acting immorally. So if pro‐life scholars really believe that human fetuses have significant moral status, they have strong moral obligations to oppose spontaneous abortion. Yet, few of them, devote any effort to doing so.

Finally, personhood is a threshold concept: foetuses only become persons once they have developed enough qualities to qualify as human beings. This is a standard response to pro-life objections, but Räsänen embellishes it with another reductio ad absurdum

A standard human fetus (or an infant) cannot value continuing of his life (or almost anything else for that matter), therefore killing it does not violate its flourishing, it only violates its future possible flourishing. The mere possibility for future flourishing as a reason for the moral status seems to be an untenable view unless one is willing to accept that cats, which could miraculously be turned into persons with a magical serum, would have same rights, before they had been injected with the serum, as human persons do. That is because they would still have a potential for flourishing like ours.

The article is certain to spark a lot of debate.

(By the way, Räsänen does acknowledge that his critics “have engaged this important topic in a respectful and civilized manner”.)

LifeNews Note: Michael Cook is editor of MercatorNet where this story appeared.